by Jeffrey Shulman
Jeffrey Shulman from Georgetown Law looks at the
unintended consequences of two statutes that could, in the words of
Justice Antonin Scalia, “permit every citizen to become a law unto
himself.”
Abdul Maalik Muhammad (or Gregory Holt)
We have all learned to be
sensitive to the many symbolic dimensions of hair. Cultural marker,
religious mandate, personal statement, good luck charm—hair matters. And
we all know that most things that matter sooner or later become the
stuff of legal conflict. Indeed, a facial hair dispute will soon be
before the Supreme Court.
Abdul Maalik Muhammad, who will
enter legal history as Gregory Holt, wants to grow a beard in accordance
with his salafi muslim faith. Though obligated by his understanding of islamic law to leave his beard entirely uncut, Mr. Holt seeks to grow
only a half-inch beard. The problem is that he is in an Arkansas state
prison, where he is serving a life sentence for burglary and domestic
battery, and state prison officials have their own set of hair dictates.
The state Department of
Correction prohibits beards, though it does allow quarter-inch beards
that are grown for medical reasons. Prison officials argue that safety
and security concerns—a half-inch beard could become a hiding place for
contraband; a prisoner who escaped could change his appearance by
shaving his beard; it would be difficult to monitor beard length; any
exceptions to a uniform grooming policy could breed resentment—require a
uniform no-beard policy. What makes this case interesting, however, is
not the merits of the department’s justifications for its grooming
policy, but the burden of proof under which the department will have to
labor. It’s the burden of proof that will decide this case—and in all
likelihood make the decision an easy one.
If Mr. Holt were claiming that
the state’s prison policy violated his right under the federal
Constitution to exercise his religious beliefs freely, things might be a
little dicier. In constitutional law, there are rights, and then there
are rights. Most laws (or other forms of state action) receive a
deferential review from the courts, despite the fact that they might
impinge upon a host of personal prerogatives. Under “rational basis
review,” courts presume the constitutionality of legislation. The party
trying to overcome this presumption must show 1) that the law serves no
legitimate purpose, or 2) that the means employed by the law has no
rational relation to the law’s stated goal.
But laws (or other forms of
state action) that impinge upon rights considered to be “fundamental”
get a far more skeptical judicial reception. Under a “strict scrutiny”
standard, courts will presume that such a law is unconstitutional. To
overcome this presumption, the government must show 1) that the law serves a compelling purpose, and 2) that the means employed by the law are as narrowly tailored as possible to achieve the law’s stated goal.
Because the hurdle of strict
scrutiny is so difficult to clear (“strict in theory and fatal in fact,”
it is commonly, if not entirely accurately, said), the level of review
employed by the court can easily determine the outcome of a case.
With regard to regulations that
incidentally burden religious practice, the Supreme Court has said that
rational basis review applies. Such restrictions are constitutionally
permissible unless they directly target religious practice or
discriminate against religious groups. This is the core principle of Employment Division, Department of Human Resources of Oregon v. Smith. Decided in 1990, the Smith
Court held that where state regulation burdens religious freedom only
incidentally—that is, where the burden is a secondary effect of a
regulation that is neutral and generally applicable, restricting secular
and religious activity alike—the courts will presume its
constitutionality. Thus, for example, a law that makes illegal the use
of peyote because of safety and health concerns—this was the case in Smith—would
be subject to, and would survive, rational basis review, even though it
would burden the beliefs and perhaps effectively prohibit the practices
of some religious groups.
Smith unleashed a
perfect storm of outrage, with blasts of criticism coming from both the
left and right sides of the political spectrum. Since 1990, critics of Smith have
sought a statutory return to the heightened review of free exercise
claims. In 1993, Congress passed the Religious Freedom Restoration Act
(RFRA), which required a strict scrutiny standard for any federal or
state action that “substantially burden[s] a person’s exercise of
religion even if the burden results from a rule of general
applicability.”
In 1997, for reasons not
relevant here, the Supreme Court overturned RFRA insofar as it applied
to the states. (Think second perfect storm.) But RFRA remains good law
where the action of the federal government is concerned. Its strict
scrutiny standard was the heavy finger that tipped the scales in favor
of Hobby Lobby’s claim that its rights were violated by Obamacare’s
contraception mandate—violated not under the Constitution, but under the
federal RFRA.
Soon after the demise of RFRA’s
application to state laws, Congress went to work to find a way to bring
heightened review to some aspects of state conduct. The result (in 2000)
was a statute with the ungainly title of the Religious Land Use and
Institutionalized Persons Act, which goes by the even more ungainly
acronym RLUIPA. In brief, RLUIPA applies strict scrutiny to claims of
religious burdens involving prisoner rights or discriminatory land use.
Which brings us back to the
question of prison grooming policies. For Mr. Holt is not suing under
the First Amendment. His claim is that Arkansas prison officials have
violated RLUIPA. Thus, to justify a uniform grooming policy, prison
officials will have to do more than show that the policy is reasonably
related to a legitimate penological interest. That’s the constitutional
standard. Under RLUIPA, prison officials will have to show that there is
a compelling state interest in a no-beard policy and that such a policy
is the least restrictive means to further this interest.
This burden will probably be too
much for the Department of Correction to bear. In trial testimony,
prison officials failed to offer much in the way of specific evidence to
demonstrate the validity of their safety and security concerns. Or
anything in the way of evidence to show why they had ruled out less
restrictive policies. (This explains why the department argues that
courts should not insist on data, studies, and examples as proof to
uphold prison officials’ predictive judgments.) It’s not going to help
the department that an exemption is already made for medical reasons.
Nor is it going to help that at least 44 state and federal prison
systems would permit Mr. Holt to grow his beard, and that 42 of these
jurisdictions would impose no length limitations whatsoever.
There’s little choice but for
state officials to fall upon the argument that courts have historically
accorded great deference to prison officials in matters of safety and
security. This is true enough, but it’s precisely this degree of
deference that the strict scrutiny standard of RLUIPA is meant to
change. In discussing strict scrutiny under RFRA (the standard is the
same under RLUIPA), the Court has said that the test contemplates an
inquiry more focused than a mere categorical approach. It “requires the
Government to demonstrate that the compelling interest test is satisfied
through application of the challenged law ‘to the person’—the
particular claimant whose sincere exercise of religion is being
substantially burdened.” These laws thus “look beyond broadly formulated
interests justifying the general applicability of government mandates
and scrutinize the asserted harm of granting specific exemptions to
particular religious claimants.”
Interestingly, the Department of
Correction did not argue with any energy that its beard policy was
appropriate given the particular religious claimant who brought this
case. Yet Mr. Holt had declared “a state of war” with the prison barber
after one beard-trimming episode. The two had to be permanently
separated. The department’s failure to pursue this line of argument is
curious. In its amicus brief supporting Mr. Holt, the United States
noted this altercation, remarking that “[i]n general, if an inmate who
is permitted to grow a half-inch beard as an accommodation creates a
security risk by initiating hostile altercations with a barber, it may
be appropriate to withdraw that accommodation to further proper security
interests.” The Solicitor General’s invitation to pursue this line of
argument is curious, too.
All of this leaves open the
question whether as a policy matter it would make more sense for courts
to defer to the judgment of prison officials. More broadly, cases like
those brought by Mr. Holt and Hobby Lobby should cause us to ask why the
constitutional standard is not the appropriate measure by which to
judge neutral and generally applicable regulations that incidentally
burden religion. Was Justice Scalia wrong in Smith to warn that
strict scrutiny review of neutral and generally applicable laws would
“make the professed doctrines of religious belief superior to the law of
the land, and in effect . . . permit every citizen to become a law unto
himself”? And should we not ask—indeed, some have—what business
Congress has in telling the Supreme Court that it must apply strict
scrutiny where the Court has already decided it is inappropriate to do
so?
There was much liberal outrage when the Supreme Court handed down Hobby Lobby.
But a strict scrutiny standard for regulations that burden religion was
the child of legislative parents liberal and wingnut. (RFRA’s
primary co-sponsors were Senators Ted Kennedy and Orrin Hatch.) Sooner
or later, strict scrutiny will deliver an unpleasant surprise to wingnuts, too. Perhaps, then, when we think about religious
objections to neutral and generally applicable regulations, the law that
we should really pay attention to is the law of unintended
consequences.
************
No comments:
Post a Comment